Reading: Meditation 5 Of the essence of material things; and, again, of God; that He exists

  1. Meditation V: What is Descartes’s point in discussing the “essence of material things”? How do these reflections lead to another proof of God’s existence? How does this proof work?
  2. How is the proof of the existence of God in Meditation 5 similar to that of Anselm? How is it different?

(1) There now only remains the inquiry as to whether material things exist. With regard to this question, I at least know with certainty that such things may exist, in as far as they constitute the object of the pure mathematics, since, regarding them in this aspect, I can conceive them clearly and distinctly. For there can be no doubt that God possesses the power of producing all the objects I am able distinctly to conceive, and I never considered anything impossible to him, unless when I experienced a contradiction in the attempt to conceive it aright. Further, the faculty of imagination which I possess, and of which I am conscious that I make use when I apply myself to the consideration of material things, is sufficient to persuade me of their existence: for, when I attentively consider what imagination is, I find that it is simply a certain application of the cognitive faculty (facultas cognoscitiva) to a body which is immediately present to it, and which therefore exists.

(2) And to render this quite clear, I remark, in the first place, the difference that subsists between imagination and pure intellection or conception . For example, when I imagine a triangle I not only conceive (intelligo) that it is a figure comprehended by three lines, but at the same time also I look upon (intueor) these three lines as present by the power and internal application of my mind (acie mentis), and this is what I call imagining. But if I desire to think of a chiliogon, I indeed rightly conceive that it is a figure composed of a thousand sides, as easily as I conceive that a triangle is a figure composed of only three sides; but I cannot imagine the thousand sides of a chiliogon as I do the three sides of a triangle, nor, so to speak, view them as present with the eyes of my mind . And although, in accordance with the habit I have of always imagining something when I think of corporeal things, it may happen that, in conceiving a chiliogon, I confusedly represent some figure to myself, yet it is quite evident that this is not a chiliogon, since it in no wise differs from that which I would represent to myself, if I were to think of a myriogon, or any other figure of many sides; nor would this representation be of any use in discovering and unfolding the properties that constitute the difference between a chiliogon and other polygons. But if the question turns on a pentagon, it is quite true that I can conceive its figure, as well as that of a chiliogon, without the aid of imagination; but I can likewise imagine it by applying the attention of my mind to its five sides, and at the same time to the area which they contain. Thus I observe that a special effort of mind is necessary to the act of imagination, which is not required to conceiving or understanding (ad intelligendum); and this special exertion of mind clearly shows the difference between imagination and pure intellection (imaginatio et intellectio pura).

(3) I remark, besides, that this power of imagination which I possess, in as far as it differs from the power of conceiving, is in no way necessary to my nature or essence, that is, to the essence of my mind; for although I did not possess it, I should still remain the same that I now am, from which it seems we may conclude that it depends on something different from the mind. And I easily understand that, if some body exists, with which my mind is so conjoined and united as to be able, as it were, to consider it when it chooses, it may thus imagine corporeal objects; so that this mode of thinking differs from pure intellection only in this respect, that the mind in conceiving turns in some way upon itself, and considers some one of the ideas it possesses within itself; but in imagining it turns toward the body, and contemplates in it some object conformed to the idea which it either of itself conceived or apprehended by sense. I easily understand, I say, that imagination may be thus formed, if it is true that there are bodies; and because I find no other obvious mode of explaining it, I thence, with probability, conjecture that they exist, but only with probability; and although I carefully examine all things, nevertheless I do not find that, from the distinct idea of corporeal nature I have in my imagination, I can necessarily infer the existence of any body.

(4) But I am accustomed to imagine many other objects besides that corporeal nature which is the object of the pure mathematics, as, for example, colors, sounds, tastes, pain, and the like, although with less distinctness; and, inasmuch as I perceive these objects much better by the senses, through the medium of which and of memory, they seem to have reached the imagination, I believe that, in order the more advantageously to examine them, it is proper I should at the same time examine what sense-perception is, and inquire whether from those ideas that are apprehended by this mode of thinking ( consciousness), I cannot obtain a certain proof of the existence of corporeal objects.

(5) And, in the first place, I will recall to my mind the things I have hitherto held as true, because perceived by the senses, and the foundations upon which my belief in their truth rested; I will, in the second place, examine the reasons that afterward constrained me to doubt of them; and, finally, I will consider what of them I ought now to believe.

(6) Firstly, then, I perceived that I had a head, hands, feet and other members composing that body which I considered as part, or perhaps even as the whole, of myself. I perceived further, that that body was placed among many others, by which it was capable of being affected in diverse ways, both beneficial and hurtful; and what was beneficial I remarked by a certain sensation of pleasure, and what was hurtful by a sensation of pain. And besides this pleasure and pain, I was likewise conscious of hunger, thirst, and other appetites, as well as certain corporeal inclinations toward joy, sadness, anger, and similar passions. And, out of myself, besides the extension, figure, and motions of bodies, I likewise perceived in them hardness, heat, and the other tactile qualities, and, in addition, light, colors, odors, tastes, and sounds, the variety of which gave me the means of distinguishing the sky, the earth, the sea, and generally all the other bodies, from one another. And certainly, considering the ideas of all these qualities, which were presented to my mind, and which alone I properly and immediately perceived, it was not without reason that I thought I perceived certain objects wholly different from my thought, namely, bodies from which those ideas proceeded; for I was conscious that the ideas were presented to me without my consent being required, so that I could not perceive any object, however desirous I might be, unless it were present to the organ of sense; and it was wholly out of my power not to perceive it when it was thus present. And because the ideas I perceived by the senses were much more lively and clear, and even, in their own way, more distinct than any of those I could of myself frame by meditation, or which I found impressed on my memory, it seemed that they could not have proceeded from myself, and must therefore have been caused in me by some other objects; and as of those objects I had no knowledge beyond what the ideas themselves gave me, nothing was so likely to occur to my mind as the supposition that the objects were similar to the ideas which they caused. And because I recollected also that I had formerly trusted to the senses, rather than to reason, and that the ideas which I myself formed were not so clear as those I perceived by sense, and that they were even for the most part composed of parts of the latter, I was readily persuaded that I had no idea in my intellect which had not formerly passed through the senses. Nor was I altogether wrong in likewise believing that that body which, by a special right, I called my own, pertained to me more properly and strictly than any of the others; for in truth, I could never be separated from it as from other bodies; I felt in it and on account of it all my appetites and affections, and in fine I was affected in its parts by pain and the titillation of pleasure, and not in the parts of the other bodies that were separated from it. But when I inquired into the reason why, from this I know not what sensation of pain, sadness of mind should follow, and why from the sensation of pleasure, joy should arise, or why this indescribable twitching of the stomach, which I call hunger, should put me in mind of taking food, and the parchedness of the throat of drink, and so in other cases, I was unable to give any explanation, unless that I was so taught by nature; for there is assuredly no affinity, at least none that I am able to comprehend, between this irritation of the stomach and the desire of food, any more than between the perception of an object that causes pain and the consciousness of sadness which springs from the perception. And in the same way it seemed to me that all the other judgments I had formed regarding the objects of sense, were dictates of nature; because I remarked that those judgments were formed in me, before I had leisure to weigh and consider the reasons that might constrain me to form them.

(7) But, afterward, a wide experience by degrees sapped the faith I had reposed in my senses; for I frequently observed that towers, which at a distance seemed round, appeared square, when more closely viewed, and that colossal figures, raised on the summits of these towers, looked like small statues, when viewed from the bottom of them; and, in other instances without number, I also discovered error in judgments founded on the external senses; and not only in those founded on the external, but even in those that rested on the internal senses; for is there aught more internal than pain ? And yet I have sometimes been informed by parties whose arm or leg had been amputated, that they still occasionally seemed to feel pain in that part of the body which they had lost, –a circumstance that led me to think that I could not be quite certain even that any one of my members was affected when I felt pain in it. And to these grounds of doubt I shortly afterward also added two others of very wide generality: the first of them was that I believed I never perceived anything when awake which I could not occasionally think I also perceived when asleep, and as I do not believe that the ideas I seem to perceive in my sleep proceed from objects external to me, I did not any more observe any ground for believing this of such as I seem to perceive when awake; the second was that since I was as yet ignorant of the author of my being or at least supposed myself to be so, I saw nothing to prevent my having been so constituted by nature as that I should be deceived even in matters that appeared to me to possess the greatest truth. And, with respect to the grounds on which I had before been persuaded of the existence of sensible objects, I had no great difficulty in finding suitable answers to them; for as nature seemed to incline me to many things from which reason made me averse, I thought that I ought not to confide much in its teachings. And although the perceptions of the senses were not dependent on my will, I did not think that I ought on that ground to conclude that they proceeded from things different from myself, since perhaps there might be found in me some faculty, though hitherto unknown to me, which produced them.

(8) But now that I begin to know myself better, and to discover more clearly the author of my being, I do not, indeed, think that I ought rashly to admit all which the senses seem to teach, nor, on the other hand, is it my conviction that I ought to doubt in general of their teachings.

(9) And, firstly, because I know that all which I clearly and distinctly conceive can be produced by God exactly as I conceive it, it is sufficient that I am able clearly and distinctly to conceive one thing apart from another, in order to be certain that the one is different from the other, seeing they may at least be made to exist separately, by the omnipotence of God; and it matters not by what power this separation is made, in order to be compelled to judge them different; and, therefore, merely because I know with certitude that I exist, and because, in the meantime, I do not observe that aught necessarily belongs to my nature or essence beyond my being a thinking thing, I rightly conclude that my essence consists only in my being a thinking thing or a substance whose whole essence or nature is merely thinking. And although I may, or rather, as I will shortly say, although I certainly do possess a body with which I am very closely conjoined; nevertheless, because, on the one hand, I have a clear and distinct idea of myself, in as far as I am only a thinking and unextended thing, and as, on the other hand, I possess a distinct idea of body, in as far as it is only an extended and unthinking thing, it is certain that I, that is, my mind, by which I am what I am, is entirely and truly distinct from my body, and may exist without it.

(10) Moreover, I find in myself diverse faculties of thinking that have each their special mode: for example, I find I possess the faculties of imagining and perceiving, without which I can indeed clearly and distinctly conceive myself as entire, but I cannot reciprocally conceive them without conceiving myself, that is to say, without an intelligent substance in which they reside, for in the notion we have of them, or to use the terms of the schools in their formal concept, they comprise some sort of intellection; whence I perceive that they are distinct from myself as modes are from things. I remark likewise certain other faculties, as the power of changing place, of assuming diverse figures, and the like, that cannot be conceived and cannot therefore exist, any more than the preceding, apart from a substance in which they inhere. It is very evident, however, that these faculties, if they really exist, must belong to some corporeal or extended substance, since in their clear and distinct concept there is contained some sort of extension, but no intellection at all. Further, I cannot doubt but that there is in me a certain passive faculty of perception, that is, of receiving and taking knowledge of the ideas of sensible things; but this would be useless to me, if there did not also exist in me, or in some other thing, another active faculty capable of forming and producing those ideas. But this active faculty cannot be in me in as far as I am but a thinking thing, seeing that it does not presuppose thought, and also that those ideas are frequently produced in my mind without my contributing to it in any way, and even frequently contrary to my will. This faculty must therefore exist in some substance different from me, in which all the objective reality of the ideas that are produced by this faculty is contained formally or eminently, as I before remarked; and this substance is either a body, that is to say, a corporeal nature in which is contained formally and in effect all that is objectively and by representation in those ideas; or it is God himself, or some other creature, of a rank superior to body, in which the same is contained eminently. But as God is no deceiver, it is manifest that he does not of himself and immediately communicate those ideas to me, nor even by the intervention of any creature in which their objective reality is not formally, but only eminently, contained. For as he has given me no faculty whereby I can discover this to be the case, but, on the contrary, a very strong inclination to believe that those ideas arise from corporeal objects, I do not see how he could be vindicated from the charge of deceit, if in truth they proceeded from any other source, or were produced by other causes than corporeal things: and accordingly it must be concluded, that corporeal objects exist. Nevertheless, they are not perhaps exactly such as we perceive by the senses, for their comprehension by the senses is, in many instances, very obscure and confused; but it is at least necessary to admit that all which I clearly and distinctly conceive as in them, that is, generally speaking all that is comprehended in the object of speculative geometry, really exists external to me.

(11) But with respect to other things which are either only particular, as, for example, that the sun is of such a size and figure, etc., or are conceived with less clearness and distinctness, as light, sound, pain, and the like, although they are highly dubious and uncertain, nevertheless on the ground alone that God is no deceiver, and that consequently he has permitted no falsity in my opinions which he has not likewise given me a faculty of correcting, I think I may with safety conclude that I possess in myself the means of arriving at the truth. And, in the first place, it cannot be doubted that in each of the dictates of nature there is some truth: for by nature, considered in general, I now understand nothing more than God himself, or the order and disposition established by God in created things; and by my nature in particular I understand the assemblage of all that God has given me.

(12) But there is nothing which that nature teaches me more expressly or more sensibly than that I have a body which is ill affected when I feel pain, and stands in need of food and drink when I experience the sensations of hunger and thirst, etc. And therefore I ought not to doubt but that there is some truth in these informations.

(13) Nature likewise teaches me by these sensations of pain, hunger, thirst, etc., that I am not only lodged in my body as a pilot in a vessel, but that I am besides so intimately conjoined, and as it were intermixed with it, that my mind and body compose a certain unity. For if this were not the case, I should not feel pain when my body is hurt, seeing I am merely a thinking thing, but should perceive the wound by the understanding alone, just as a pilot perceives by sight when any part of his vessel is damaged; and when my body has need of food or drink, I should have a clear knowledge of this, and not be made aware of it by the confused sensations of hunger and thirst: for, in truth, all these sensations of hunger, thirst, pain, etc., are nothing more than certain confused modes of thinking, arising from the union and apparent fusion of mind and body.

(14) Besides this, nature teaches me that my own body is surrounded by many other bodies, some of which I have to seek after, and others to shun. And indeed, as I perceive different sorts of colors, sounds, odors, tastes, heat, hardness, etc., I safely conclude that there are in the bodies from which the diverse perceptions of the senses proceed, certain varieties corresponding to them, although, perhaps, not in reality like them; and since, among these diverse perceptions of the senses, some are agreeable, and others disagreeable, there can be no doubt that my body, or rather my entire self, in as far as I am composed of body and mind, may be variously affected, both beneficially and hurtfully, by surrounding bodies.

(15) But there are many other beliefs which though seemingly the teaching of nature, are not in reality so, but which obtained a place in my mind through a habit of judging inconsiderately of things. It may thus easily happen that such judgments shall contain error: thus, for example, the opinion I have that all space in which there is nothing to affect or make an impression on my senses is void: that in a hot body there is something in every respect similar to the idea of heat in my mind; that in a white or green body there is the same whiteness or greenness which I perceive; that in a bitter or sweet body there is the same taste, and so in other instances; that the stars, towers, and all distant bodies, are of the same size and figure as they appear to our eyes, etc. But that I may avoid everything like indistinctness of conception, I must accurately define what I properly understand by being taught by nature. For nature is here taken in a narrower sense than when it signifies the sum of all the things which God has given me; seeing that in that meaning the notion comprehends much that belongs only to the mind to which I am not here to be understood as referring when I use the term nature; as, for example, the notion I have of the truth, that what is done cannot be undone, and all the other truths I discern by the natural light without the aid of the body; and seeing that it comprehends likewise much besides that belongs only to body, and is not here any more contained under the name nature, as the quality of heaviness, and the like, of which I do not speak, the term being reserved exclusively to designate the things which God has given to me as a being composed of mind and body. But nature, taking the term in the sense explained, teaches me to shun what causes in me the sensation of pain, and to pursue what affords me the sensation of pleasure, and other things of this sort; but I do not discover that it teaches me, in addition to this, from these diverse perceptions of the senses, to draw any conclusions respecting external objects without a previous careful and mature consideration of them by the mind: for it is, as appears to me, the office of the mind alone, and not of the composite whole of mind and body, to discern the truth in those matters. Thus, although the impression a star makes on my eye is not larger than that from the flame of a candle, I do not, nevertheless, experience any real or positive impulse determining me to believe that the star is not greater than the flame; the true account of the matter being merely that I have so judged from my youth without any rational ground. And, though on approaching the fire I feel heat, and even pain on approaching it too closely, I have, however, from this no ground for holding that something resembling the heat I feel is in the fire, any more than that there is something similar to the pain; all that I have ground for believing is, that there is something in it, whatever it may be, which excites in me those sensations of heat or pain. So also, although there are spaces in which I find nothing to excite and affect my senses, I must not therefore conclude that those spaces contain in them no body; for I see that in this, as in many other similar matters, I have been accustomed to pervert the order of nature, because these perceptions of the senses, although given me by nature merely to signify to my mind what things are beneficial and hurtful to the composite whole of which it is a part, and being sufficiently clear and distinct for that purpose, are nevertheless used by me as infallible rules by which to determine immediately the essence of the bodies that exist out of me, of which they can of course afford me only the most obscure and confused knowledge.

(16) But I have already sufficiently considered how it happens that, notwithstanding the supreme goodness of God, there is falsity in my judgments. A difficulty, however, here presents itself, respecting the things which I am taught by nature must be pursued or avoided, and also respecting the internal sensations in which I seem to have occasionally detected error, and thus to be directly deceived by nature: thus, for example, I may be so deceived by the agreeable taste of some viand with which poison has been mixed, as to be induced to take the poison. In this case, however, nature may be excused, for it simply leads me to desire the viand for its agreeable taste, and not the poison, which is unknown to it; and thus we can infer nothing from this circumstance beyond that our nature is not omniscient; at which there is assuredly no ground for surprise, since, man being of a finite nature, his knowledge must likewise be of a limited perfection.

(17) But we also not infrequently err in that to which we are directly impelled by nature, as is the case with invalids who desire drink or food that would be hurtful to them. It will here, perhaps, be alleged that the reason why such persons are deceived is that their nature is corrupted; but this leaves the difficulty untouched, for a sick man is not less really the creature of God than a man who is in full health; and therefore it is as repugnant to the goodness of God that the nature of the former should be deceitful as it is for that of the latter to be so. And as a clock, composed of wheels and counter weights, observes not the less accurately all the laws of nature when it is ill made, and points out the hours incorrectly, than when it satisfies the desire of the maker in every respect; so likewise if the body of man be considered as a kind of machine, so made up and composed of bones, nerves, muscles, veins, blood, and skin, that although there were in it no mind, it would still exhibit the same motions which it at present manifests involuntarily, and therefore without the aid of the mind, and simply by the dispositions of its organs, I easily discern that it would also be as natural for such a body, supposing it dropsical, for example, to experience the parchedness of the throat that is usually accompanied in the mind by the sensation of thirst, and to be disposed by this parchedness to move its nerves and its other parts in the way required for drinking, and thus increase its malady and do itself harm, as it is natural for it, when it is not indisposed to be stimulated to drink for its good by a similar cause; and although looking to the use for which a clock was destined by its maker, I may say that it is deflected from its proper nature when it incorrectly indicates the hours, and on the same principle, considering the machine of the human body as having been formed by God for the sake of the motions which it usually manifests, although I may likewise have ground for thinking that it does not follow the order of its nature when the throat is parched and drink does not tend to its preservation, nevertheless I yet plainly discern that this latter acceptation of the term nature is very different from the other: for this is nothing more than a certain denomination, depending entirely on my thought, and hence called extrinsic, by which I compare a sick man and an imperfectly constructed clock with the idea I have of a man in good health and a well made clock; while by the other acceptation of nature is understood something which is truly found in things, and therefore possessed of some truth.

(18) But certainly, although in respect of a dropsical body, it is only by way of exterior denomination that we say its nature is corrupted, when, without requiring drink, the throat is parched; yet, in respect of the composite whole, that is, of the mind in its union with the body, it is not a pure denomination, but really an error of nature, for it to feel thirst when drink would be hurtful to it: and, accordingly, it still remains to be considered why it is that the goodness of God does not prevent the nature of man thus taken from being fallacious.

(19) To commence this examination accordingly, I here remark, in the first place, that there is a vast difference between mind and body, in respect that body, from its nature, is always divisible, and that mind is entirely indivisible. For in truth, when I consider the mind, that is, when I consider myself in so far only as I am a thinking thing, I can distinguish in myself no parts, but I very clearly discern that I am somewhat absolutely one and entire; and although the whole mind seems to be united to the whole body, yet, when a foot, an arm, or any other part is cut off, I am conscious that nothing has been taken from my mind; nor can the faculties of willing, perceiving, conceiving, etc., properly be called its parts, for it is the same mind that is exercised all entire in willing, in perceiving, and in conceiving, etc. But quite the opposite holds in corporeal or extended things; for I cannot imagine any one of them how small soever it may be, which I cannot easily sunder in thought, and which, therefore, I do not know to be divisible. This would be sufficient to teach me that the mind or soul of man is entirely different from the body, if I had not already been apprised of it on other grounds.

(20) I remark, in the next place, that the mind does not immediately receive the impression from all the parts of the body, but only from the brain, or perhaps even from one small part of it, viz, that in which the common sense (senses communis) is said to be, which as often as it is affected in the same way gives rise to the same perception in the mind, although meanwhile the other parts of the body may be diversely disposed, as is proved by innumerable experiments, which it is unnecessary here to enumerate.

(21) I remark, besides, that the nature of body is such that none of its parts can be moved by another part a little removed from the other, which cannot likewise be moved in the same way by any one of the parts that lie between those two, although the most remote part does not act at all. As, for example, in the cord A, B, C, D, which is in tension, if its last part D, be pulled, the first part A, will not be moved in a different way than it would be were one of the intermediate parts B or C to be pulled, and the last part D meanwhile to remain fixed. And in the same way, when I feel pain in the foot, the science of physics teaches me that this sensation is experienced by means of the nerves dispersed over the foot, which, extending like cords from it to the brain, when they are contracted in the foot, contract at the same time the inmost parts of the brain in which they have their origin, and excite in these parts a certain motion appointed by nature to cause in the mind a sensation of pain, as if existing in the foot; but as these nerves must pass through the tibia, the leg, the loins, the back, and neck, in order to reach the brain, it may happen that although their extremities in the foot are not affected, but only certain of their parts that pass through the loins or neck, the same movements, nevertheless, are excited in the brain by this motion as would have been caused there by a hurt received in the foot, and hence the mind will necessarily feel pain in the foot, just as if it had been hurt; and the same is true of all the other perceptions of our senses.

(22) I remark, finally, that as each of the movements that are made in the part of the brain by which the mind is immediately affected, impresses it with but a single sensation, the most likely supposition in the circumstances is, that this movement causes the mind to experience, among all the sensations which it is capable of impressing upon it; that one which is the best fitted, and generally the most useful for the preservation of the human body when it is in full health. But experience shows us that all the perceptions which nature has given us are of such a kind as I have mentioned; and accordingly, there is nothing found in them that does not manifest the power and goodness of God. Thus, for example, when the nerves of the foot are violently or more than usually shaken, the motion passing through the medulla of the spine to the innermost parts of the brain affords a sign to the mind on which it experiences a sensation, viz, of pain, as if it were in the foot, by which the mind is admonished and excited to do its utmost to remove the cause of it as dangerous and hurtful to the foot. It is true that God could have so constituted the nature of man as that the same motion in the brain would have informed the mind of something altogether different: the motion might, for example, have been the occasion on which the mind became conscious of itself, in so far as it is in the brain, or in so far as it is in some place intermediate between the foot and the brain, or, finally, the occasion on which it perceived some other object quite different, whatever that might be; but nothing of all this would have so well contributed to the preservation of the body as that which the mind actually feels. In the same way, when we stand in need of drink, there arises from this want a certain parchedness in the throat that moves its nerves, and by means of them the internal parts of the brain; and this movement affects the mind with the sensation of thirst, because there is nothing on that occasion which is more useful for us than to be made aware that we have need of drink for the preservation of our health; and so in other instances.

(23) Whence it is quite manifest that, notwithstanding the sovereign goodness of God, the nature of man, in so far as it is composed of mind and body, cannot but be sometimes fallacious. For, if there is any cause which excites, not in the foot, but in some one of the parts of the nerves that stretch from the foot to the brain, or even in the brain itself, the same movement that is ordinarily created when the foot is ill affected, pain will be felt, as it were, in the foot, and the sense will thus be naturally deceived; for as the same movement in the brain can but impress the mind with the same sensation, and as this sensation is much more frequently excited by a cause which hurts the foot than by one acting in a different quarter, it is reasonable that it should lead the mind to feel pain in the foot rather than in any other part of the body. And if it sometimes happens that the parchedness of the throat does not arise, as is usual, from drink being necessary for the health of the body, but from quite the opposite cause, as is the case with the dropsical, yet it is much better that it should be deceitful in that instance, than if, on the contrary, it were continually fallacious when the body is well-disposed; and the same holds true in other cases.

(24) And certainly this consideration is of great service, not only in enabling me to recognize the errors to which my nature is liable, but likewise in rendering it more easy to avoid or correct them: for, knowing that all my senses more usually indicate to me what is true than what is false, in matters relating to the advantage of the body, and being able almost always to make use of more than a single sense in examining the same object, and besides this, being able to use my memory in connecting present with past knowledge, and my understanding which has already discovered all the causes of my errors, I ought no longer to fear that falsity may be met with in what is daily presented to me by the senses. And I ought to reject all the doubts of those bygone days, as hyperbolical and ridiculous, especially the general uncertainty respecting sleep, which I could not distinguish from the waking state: for I now find a very marked difference between the two states, in respect that our memory can never connect our dreams with each other and with the course of life, in the way it is in the habit of doing with events that occur when we are awake. And, in truth, if some one, when I am awake, appeared to me all of a sudden and as suddenly disappeared, as do the images I see in sleep, so that I could not observe either whence he came or whither he went, I should not without reason esteem it either a specter or phantom formed in my brain, rather than a real man. But when I perceive objects with regard to which I can distinctly determine both the place whence they come, and that in which they are, and the time at which they appear to me, and when, without interruption, I can connect the perception I have of them with the whole of the other parts of my life, I am perfectly sure that what I thus perceive occurs while I am awake and not during sleep. And I ought not in the least degree to doubt of the truth of these presentations, if, after having called together all my senses, my memory, and my understanding for the purpose of examining them, no deliverance is given by any one of these faculties which is repugnant to that of any other: for since God is no deceiver, it necessarily follows that I am not herein deceived. But because the necessities of action frequently oblige us to come to a determination before we have had leisure for so careful an examination, it must be confessed that the life of man is frequently obnoxious to error with respect to individual objects; and we must, in conclusion, ac. knowledge the weakness of our nature.

What’s going on in Meditation 6?

In Meditation VI, Descartes makes the argument that completes his “case” for “firm and constant knowledge in the sciences.” There are a number of interesting points in this meditation (such as Descartes’ theory about the relationship between mind and body), but let’s begin with knowledge of material things, which lies at the heart of scientific knowledge.

As we have seen, my understanding gives me the ability to think ideas as having certain determinate features and characteristics For instance, the understanding allows me to grasp the “essence” of the concept of a triangle. However, whenever I form an image of a triangle, something more is involved. The image involves “materials” that I draw from sense experience: imagining lines, size, color, texture etc. These sensible qualities are different from strictly understanding the concept of triangle. In other words, whenever you imaging a triangle, you have to imagine something — either a scalene, isosceles, or equilateral triangle — and you cannot imagine the triangle being all of these at the same time. (These geometry terms refer to the lengths of the sides: “scalene” means the triangle has no sides of the same length, “isosceles” means exactly two sides of the same length, and “equilateral” means all three sides are the same length.) In other words, when you “picture” a triangle, you picture a specific triangle. You can’t imagine a triangle “in general.”

On the other hand, when you understand the concept “triangle,” your understanding of it takes all of these different types of triangles into account, all at the same time. This illustrates that there’s a difference between the understanding and the imagination.

Descartes argues that the imagination, the faculty that allows me to form images of things, requires more effort than the understanding. What he means is that, whenever we understand an idea, the act of “understanding” is spontaneous, but when we “conjure” up an image of something, we have to make an effort to attend to it and hold the image in mind. Now the important thing about images is that they always involve particular traits, such as size or motion, and these traits cannot be understood except as applying to material bodies. In a sense, then, whenever I imagine things, I must assume that there must be material things from which these qualities derive.

In simpler terms, whenever I think of things in images, I cannot help but assume that there are material things that provide me the “materials” to work with — pun intended. But there are only two options: (1) either there are material things or (2) not. If (2) is correct, and if I cannot help believe in them anyway whenever I form images of things, then — since God gave me the mental abilities involved in imagining things — God must be a deceiver. However, God cannot be a deceiver (as we established in Meditation III), so (2) cannot be correct. That leaves (1): There are material things that “have” the properties that are the source of my images.

A little review of Aristotle will help us. Recall that Aristotle argues that traits are “in” the things of which they are traits — like Matthew’s obnoxiousness, which depends for its existence on the existence of the primary substance, Matthew. This “in” relation forms the background of Descartes’s argument here. When I imagine something, I cannot help assuming that the traits that I use to imagine it must come from actual traits that are actually in actual things.

The most vivid example may be my own body: My mental activity includes sensations that I cannot help but refer to my body as an actual thing. So, if (2) were correct, my referring these sensations to my body would be illusory, since there would be no body to refer them to. But that would mean I am actually something like a “mind in a bottle” — in which case God would have arranged everything to make me believe I had a body when in fact I do not. But since God cannot deceive, the fact that I refer sensations to my body cannot be illusory (even though I might be mistaken on occasion). So, I have a body. The same sort of reasoning applies to material things outside me (other than my body). If this is so, then, using our equipment correctly (remember the “mismatch” of the will and the understanding from IV!), we can achieve true knowledge of material things.

Notice that this argument is generic and really has to do with how our equipment works “in general.” If God had made me a mind-in-a-bottle, I would always be mistaken when attributing traits to material objects. Even so, we can still be mistaken about a particular judgment about things in the external world. Descartes’ point is that although God has not arranged things so that I am never mistaken about external material things, God cannot possibly have made me so that I am always mistaken about external material things — for the simple reason that God cannot be the source of deception.

Think this through: There is an important difference between being sometimes wrong and always wrong about the images we form of things. And this difference is what allows us — finite minds that we are — to achieve genuine science, when we use the will and the understanding properly.

Excursion: George Berkeley

Descartes’s goal in the Meditations is to put scientific knowledge on a solid foundation. The move we just examined is an central part of that project: If my disposition to refer my sense experience to an external material world is systematically mistaken, then God must have made me to be systematically deceived by my experience — which makes God a deceiver. Since deceit is inconsistent with God’s nature, my sense experience does refer to an external material world. This puts the use of my equipment — the will and the understanding — at the center of the project. This is also why Descartes is nicknamed the “Father of Modern Philosophy”: Because of his focus on methodology, the foundation of philosophy shifts from metaphysics to epistemology. (This is hugely oversimplified, as most slogans are. But it capture something about how Descartes is read — and taught! — today.)

As you might expect, philosophers challenged various steps in Descartes’s argument, and in this short excursion, we will look at one objector, George Berkeley (1685—1753). (“Berkeley” is pronounced barkley.)

Speaking of slogans, Berkeley is most famous for his statement, esse est percipii, which means “to be is to be perceived.” What he means by this is straightforward: If you think about it, we have no access to anything outside the mind. All we have access to are our ideas: All the thoughts and perceptions that you use to navigate the world, sense your body, etc. — all of that mental activity takes place entirely within your mind.

So far, Descartes and Berkeley agree: Mental activity is, well, mental. But whereas Descartes uses God’s nature to “connect” ideas in the mind with things in the external world, Berkeley uses God’s nature to jettison the external world completely! Let’s see how this works.

Berkeley argues that what “makes” something real is being perceived by a mind. In other words, the reason I experience my espresso cup as real is because I perceive it. If for some reason I stopped perceiving my espresso cup in any way — sight, touch, etc. — then I would not think of it as real.

Now, you might be thinking, Surely things don’t cease to exist when we stop perceiving them! Suppose I put my espresso cup in the cupboard and close the door. Now I’m not perceiving it, but I don’t seriously doubt that it continues to exist in the cupboard.

Fair enough, Berkeley would say. That is indeed our experience. But this persistence of real things doesn’t have to be explained by an appeal to external material objects, the way Descartes does. Rather, Berkeley proposes that the cup “stays real” when we aren’t perceiving it because there is a mind that continues to perceive the cup when we don’t or can’t. And that mind is — God.

In Berkeley’s theory, God perceives everything, and what God perceives is the set of real things. But they are nevertheless perceptions — meaning, there is no need to propose any physical reality “underlying” the realness of material objects. Instead, the “realness” of every real thing derives from it being perceived by God. To oversimplify a bit, reality is constituted by God’s mental activity. When we perceive something, we are in fact perceiving a subset of God’s perceptions.

Now here’s the real challenge to Descartes’s argument: Berkeley does not think that our disposition to refer perceptions to external material objects is deception on God’s part. On the contrary, once we realize that to be is “to be perceived,” then it’s actually our fault if we wrongly attribute realness to the material nature of objects — especially because we have absolutely no way to access the material nature of anything. All we have access to is our own mental activity.

Interestingly, Berkeley’s theory doesn’t necessarily do away with science. In fact, scientific truth, like all other truth, turns out to be a subset of ideas in the mind of God. Our challenge lies not in getting access to physical objects; our challenge lies in how to know some of what God knows.

Minds and Bodies

Now let’s get back to Descartes. There’s a lot going on in Meditation VI, but let’s notice only one other issue: the “mind-body problem.” Descartes argues that  mind and body are completely different types of “stuff,” thinking substance and extended substance. This view has come to be known as “Cartesian Dualism.” Nevertheless, he points out that my mind and body are “intermingled, so that I and the body form a unit.” This is the interesting claim: If my body and mind are in fact completely different kinds of stuff, then how do they “intermingle”?  A more striking way to ask this question involve the “connection” between mind and body. If they really are completely different, how do they communicate with each other?

Picture a situation in which we are trying to communicate. I speak only Japanese and you speak only Spanish. If we have no other means of communication than our own languages, then we won’t communicate at all, since Japanese and Spanish are “completely different.” If communication is to be possible, one of three options must be true: (1) I also speak (some) Spanish; (2) you also speak (some) Japanese; or (3) some third speaker is involved, who speaks both Japanese and Spanish. In claiming that thinking substance and extended substance are completely different kinds of stuff, Descartes seems to be denying all three possibilities: (1) and (2) involve some “overlap” between mind and body, and (3) brings in some third kind of stuff other than minds and bodies. In spite of this, Descartes still seems to have believed that mind and body “connect” in a weird, physical way: In fact, he claims that the soul is plugged into the body in the pineal gland deep in the brain.

This issue — how do mind and body “connect” — is called the “mind-body problem.” Obviously, a lot more could be said about Descartes’ version of it and subsequent philosophers’ efforts to “solve” the problem. For instance, someone might argue that God brings about the communication between mind and body. This may make some sense if one accepts the existence of God (as defined by Descartes, et al.), but it does raise questions. Does this mean that the mind and body run on parallel “tracks” on which events are synchronized but nevertheless disconnected? In other words, does God merely keep mind and body synchronized — like two (unconnected) clocks? If so, what can we make of Descartes’s claim that mind and body are “intermingled”?

These reflections raise one of the deepest questions facing the sisters as they consider what to do about Matthew: What constitutes the person? Is it a soul merely housed in a body? By this point in our exploration, it’s pretty obvious that this question isn’t about what we say about persons; rather, it’s about the underlying nature of persons. In other words, it’s a question about what is real. But tangled up in this question is this: How can we get in a position to know about persons? And if that isn’t thorny enough, What do our answers to these questions reveal about what we ought we do about Matthew’s situation?

Descartes defends a version of dualism that embraces both minds and bodies — but this view poses challenges about their connection. Even so, his perspective allows us to start mapping out some possibilities about the nature of persons. From the perspective of metaphysics, there seem to be (at least) three possibilities:

  • both the mind (thinking substance, the soul, etc.) and the body (extended substance) are fundamentally real yet different “substances.”
  • the mind is fundamentally real, and the body isn’t (This is why I brought up Berkeley’s challenge.) In this case, we have a version of “monism” (one kind of real thing, mind); this perspective is often called idealism. In this view, the body is somehow derivative or dependent on the more basic reality, the mind.
  • the body is fundamentally real, and the mind isn’t, another version of monism. In this view, the mind is somehow derivative or dependent on the body. This view is often called materialism.

All three of these possibilities revolve around the idea of substance: the fundamental “stuff” of reality. In the history of Western philosophy — at least in the dominant view — substance is understood in much the way Aristotle defines “primary beings,” namely, the individual, self-identical, persistent entities on which everything else depends for its existence. This more general view is called “substance metaphysics.” Given the dominance of that view, the question has been, What kinds of substances are there? Of course, other questions follow: How do substances relate to everything else? And how to substances relate to the question of what we ought to do?

You probably recognize in these questions the three basic sub-disciplines of philosophy that I raised at the beginning of our exploration: metaphysics, epistemology, and value theory. For much of the history of Western philosophy, these questions have been pursued within the framework of substance metaphysics — but it’s not the only game in town, even within the Western philosophical tradition. There are dissenters — like Heraclitus — and there are philosophers whose critique of traditional models show us the problems of substance metaphysics. Our final philosopher in this course, David Hume, is one of those.


Questions for conversation

  • What is Descartes’s theory concerning the connection of mind and body? Why does he reject the “pilot in his ship” model?
  • What is Cartesian Dualism? What problems arise as a result of this model of the relationship between mind and body? Why is Cartesian Dualism a version of substance metaphysics?
  • How does Berkeley account for knowledge of the world? Why is his perspective a challenge for Descartes’s line of thought?
  • If you want some serious philosophical fun, try this: Can you think of any alternatives to substance metaphysics? How would the sisters’ quandary look different from an alternative perspective?

Cutting Board

Sam and Alex arrived just before lunch, so they joined Beth at the coffeeshop. They spent lunch catching up and planning the dinner party that evening. Everything seemed to fall into place as they finished eating, so they ordered a round of espresso drinks.

“Here you go,” Alex says, handing Beth a flat white.

“What, no mocha, Sam?” Beth notes.

“Not in the mood,” Sam said, taking her espresso from Alex.

“And in this case, ‘not in the mood’ actually means that Sam made her famous flourless chocolate torte for the party,” Alex says, taking her cappuccino off the tray. “She’s just saving up.” They laugh together, and Beth couldn’t help thinking, It’s like nothing’s happened. Then she has an inspiration.

“Here’s to finishing Meditation VI,” she proclaims, raising her cup. Sam and Alex join the toast, and Beth goes on: “We finally know how we know what we know, and we know for sure that we don’t know what we can’t know.” She’s very amused at herself, and they laugh again.

“That might be a bit premature,” Alex teases.

“I knew I could count on you!” Beth teases back. “But what’s your beef with Descartes this time?”

“Where do I begin?” Alex continues dramatically. “His whole argument for knowledge hinges on God not being a deceiver — so the whole argument is only as strong as the arguments for the existence of God.”

“Come on,” Beth responds, equally dramatically. “You just don’t want to get in Descartes.” Beth exaggerated des-cartes”to convey her joke.

“Ugh! You’ve already used that joke! And it wasn’t great the first time!” Alex jibes.

“OK,,” Sam says, putting her espresso cup back on the little wooden tray and standing up. “You know what, girls? I think I’ll just go buy some wine.” They all laugh.

“You know what they say,” Alex says, seizing her moment. “If you can’t stand the heat—“

“Stay out of Descartes,” Alex and Beth say together.

“And we didn’t rehearse that!” Alex laughs.


Sam heads for the wine shop a couple blocks away, leaving the sisters linger over their empty cups, still entertained by their Descartes jokes.

“I could go for another coffee,” Alex says at last.

“Let’s do,” Beth agrees. “It’s on me — besides, I’ve been here so often that I got one of their cards.”

As they settled into another round, Beth says, “Seriously. Meditation VI — I don’t know where to start either.”

“Well,” Alex says, “I wasn’t really exaggerating much. If the argument from the mind-in-a-bottle story to firm and constant knowledge means we have to prove that God exists, it seems like that’s a big problem.”

“Yeah,” Beth says, swirling her drink.

She always swirls drinks when she’s thinking hard, Alex observes, but only to herself.

“I mean, it’s not about believing in God. It’s about whether the argument actually proves anything, right?” Beth continues.

“Yes, exactly. That’s my point. Remember Matthew’s comment about Plato? Something like, Do we think the arguments are convincing because we alreadybelieve the conclusion? It’s pretty hard to separate what you already believe from what an argument actually proves.”

“Right — just look at the discussion board. You have people saying the argument works, and you have people saying no way. But a few of the people started with things like I believe in God, but. . . .”

“Or I don’t,” Alex adds.

“Yeah,” Beth acknowledges. “So are we just stuck with what we already believed?”

“Surely we can change our minds,” Alex reflects, thinking about her own mind.

“Well, yeah,” Beth agrees, “but it’s still pretty hard.” She goes back to swirling. “Why is it so hard, do you think?”

“Well, taking a cue from big brother,” Alex answers, “it’s sort of like breathing. We just take for granted the things we believe that make the world make sense to us. So when we try to look at things from a different perspective, I don’t know — it just feels wrong, like when your shoes don’t fit.”

“Yes,” Beth says, “even when there’s plenty of evidence and arguments. I mean, I should know this. One thing data science has taught me is that people generally don’t change their minds based on evidence. It’s like Matthew says in that argument unit. It’s about motivation, and a lot of motivations to believe stuff aren’t about data. Or arguments.” More swirling, which Alex finds amusing because there didn’t seem to be anything left if the cup. “You know, sis, it is like shoes fitting, isn’t it? We just like the . . . the comfort? It’s like we’re safe somehow, if we keep seeing the world in a familiar way.”

“Wow, that’s some wine shop!” Sam interrupts the sisters’ reverie. “Way too many choices!”

“I knew you’d like it,” Beth says, giving her cup one last pointless swirl. “OK, my turn. I’m off to do the shopping. Is your offer still good?”

“Of course!” Sam says, fishing the car key out of her purse.

“Just be careful!” Alex adds with mock-concern. “We just paid it off.”

“You can trust me,” Beth says, with equal mock-concern.


“There’s something I love about this space,” Sam says as she and Alex rearrange the living room. “It’s cozy, but versatile, and—“

“And definitely Matthew,” Alex quips.

“I was going to say clean!” They laughed. When they had the living room rearranged, Sam drifts around the apartment, taking a tour of Matthew’s photos and ritual masks from all over the world. She recognized some from Africa, Indonesia, Mexico.

Sam broke off her tour to join Alex in the kitchen. “There’s no diploma,” she said.

“Nope. Just masks and photos.”

“Do you find that a little. . . . I mean. . . .“ Sam pauses. “I just never noticed that before.”

“Totally Matthew,” Alex says. “His office at the college is like an extension of this.” She nods toward door and the living room.

“I guess you’re right,” Sam reflects. “That is in character.”

“Yep,” Alex confirmed, then she continues, “Matthew used to tell this story. HR decided all the professors had to sign an acknowledgement of the college’s drug and alcohol policy, right. So Matthew reported to the campus administrator’s office to sign. When she pulled out his form, she hesitated, saying there must be a typo. Matthew would act like he was scrutinizing the form, not finding anything wrong, until the administrator pointed to the Ph.D. after his name and said, ‘That can’t be right. Are you really a doctor?’ And Matthew would laugh like a maniac and say, ‘So I told her, they give practically anybody a doctorate nowadays.’” They giggled, as much from the memory of Matthew’s laugh as anything. “So yeah, totally in character.”

Their laugh died down, leaving only the sounds of a knife on a cutting board.

“Alex,” Sam says softly, “you said used to tell.”

Alex pauses. “Yes, I did, didn’t I?”

“So . . .”

“Well, I suppose I could rationalize that. You know, his brain injury . . . well, destruction, really. He’s not going to be able to. . . .” Alex pauses again. “Anyway, I could rationalize, but that’s not it, really. Even after all the arguments, I just don’t see. . . .”

“It’s OK,” Sam says. “I get it. I mean, that basic orientation thing you’ve talked about. I don’t see it either.”

“Yeah,” Alex sighs. “But does that mean I’m just stubborn, and stuck in my own way of thinking? I mean, I really try to see these arguments from the other side, and even when things make sense, I’m just not . . . not. . . .”

“Convinced?” Sam ventures.

“Exactly — not convinced.”

“But what about Matthew?” Sam asks.

“What about Matthew?” Alex responds.

“Was he convinced? I mean, he must have thought . . . something.”

“I really don’t know,” Alex said with obvious resignation in her voice. “I mean, in some ways, he was, like, hyper-rational about things. But then he surrounds himself with ritual masks.”

“And books,” Sam observes.

“Yeah, books. You know, Matthew had this maddening thing he did, since we were kids. He always found something about any perspective that made sense, and then he would sort of slap you with it. It’s like he could put himself into different perspectives like . . . like changing clothes. Arun says he was exactly like that in class — no one ever knew what he thought.”

“Didn’t anyone ever ask him?” Sam asks. As soon as it came out, she realized how Alex might take it. “I didn’t mean. . . .”

“No, it’s OK. The weird thing is, no, I never asked. But I didn’t think I needed to.”

“Right. How could you, how could anyone foresee needing to know something like that.” Sam and Alex had prepped what they could until Beth arrived with the shopping, so they were just leaning against the counters. “Maybe he never decided,” Sam muses.

“Maybe you’re right,” Alex says, reflecting on Matthew’s instructions. “Maybe that’s what’s behind it all.”

“Is that plausible?” Sam asks.

“I suppose,” Alex acknowledges. “But then again, it’s also plausible that Matthew thought it would make a good thought experiment. Or a joke.”

“Or a good story to tell,” Sam adds.

“For someone who communicated mostly in stories and parables and sayings, that actually makes some sense,” Alex laughs.

Just then, they heard a knock and Beth’s voice through the door. “Help!”

“Time to get serious,” Alex says, heading for the door to rescue Beth from the shopping bags.

Are you struggling with your paper? Let us handle it - WE ARE EXPERTS!

Whatever paper you need - we will help you write it

Get started

Starts at $9 /page

How our paper writing service works

It's very simple!

  • Fill out the order form

    Complete the order form by providing as much information as possible, and then click the submit button.

  • Choose writer

    Select your preferred writer for the project, or let us assign the best writer for you.

  • Add funds

    Allocate funds to your wallet. You can release these funds to the writer incrementally, after each section is completed and meets your expected quality.

  • Ready

    Download the finished work. Review the paper and request free edits if needed. Optionally, rate the writer and leave a review.